Research

Gerhard Richter, Hirsch

A central goal of my research is to develop a systematic interpretation of Kant’s account of the subjective and empirical elements of human cognition. My aim in doing so is two-fold. First, many of Kant’s most important arguments rely crucially on the distinction between the objective and the subjective, and I believe an inaccurate view of the latter has tended to obscure these arguments. Second, by attending to these elements of his account, I hope to show that he has a less intellectualist and idealized—and therefore, more compelling—view of human psychology than is sometimes thought.

A unifying area of focus in my work has been the comparatively neglected but necessary role played by the imagination in Kant’s account. I defend a novel reading of the relation between the contributions of the cognitive faculties of imagination and understanding. I argue that the connections and differences between these contributions underlie Kant’s central distinction between objective and subjective validity and also shed light on his discussions of synthesis, empirical self-consciousness, empirical concepts, judgments of beauty, error and prejudice, as well as his response to his predecessors.

My published papers are available at PhilPeople.

Papers

Is it the Understanding or the Imagination that Synthesizes?Kant-Studien, 113 (3): 535-554, 2022. (Abstract)

A common reading of Kant’s notion of synthesis takes it to be carried out by the imagination in a manner guided by the concepts of the understanding. I point to a significant problem for this reading: it is the reproductive imagination that carries out the syntheses of apprehension and reproduction, and Kant claims repeatedly that the reproductive imagination is governed solely by its own laws of association. In light of this, I argue for a different division of the labor of synthesis between the imagination and the understanding. On my view, while the reproductive imagination puts representations together in accordance with laws of association, the understanding recognizes (some of) these combinations of representations as necessary in virtue of corresponding to a connection in the objects represented. I conclude by suggesting that a virtue of my account is that it can make sense of Kant’s claim that the relational categories are merely regulative for intuitions.

“Form and Matter in Kant’s Account of Self-Consciousness,” Forthcoming in The Aristotelian Kant, eds. Thomas Land and Wolfram Gobsch, Cambridge University Press.

Kant on Common Sense and Empirical Concepts," Kantian Review 27(2): 257-277, 2022. (Abstract)

Kant’s notion of common sense (Gemeinsinn) is crucial not only for his account of judgements of beauty, but also for the link he draws between the necessary conditions of such judgements and cognition in general. Contrary to existing interpretations which connect common sense to pleasure, I argue that it should be understood as the capacity to sense the harmony of the cognitive faculties through a sui generis sensation distinct from pleasure. This sensed harmony of the faculties is not only the ground of judgements of beauty and the basis of pleasure in the beautiful, but is also essential, I argue, for the reflecting judgements through which we acquire empirical concepts.

Kant on Empirical Self-Consciousness,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2021. (Abstract)

Kant is said to be the first to distinguish between consciousness of oneself as the subject of one’s experiences and consciousness of oneself as an object, which he calls transcendental and empirical apperception, respectively. Of these, it is empirical apperception that is meant to enable consciousness of any empirical features of oneself; what this amounts to, however, continues to puzzle interpreters. I argue that a key to understanding what empirical apperception consists in is Kant’s claim that each type of apperception corresponds to a distinct type of unity of apperception—that is, a distinct way in which representations can be related for a subject. Whereas transcendental unity of apperception requires that representations be actively combined by the understanding, empirical unity of apperception obtains when representations are passively combined by the reproductive imagination. In light of this, I develop a novel account of Kant’s two types of apperception, according to which they correspond to a cognitive subject’s consciousness of two essential aspects of herself—namely, her spontaneity and receptivity.

Watkins on Kant’s Laws of Nature,” Kantian Review 26 (2): 307-314, 2021. (Abstract)

I discuss three sets of worries concerning Watkins’ account of laws of nature in Kant on Laws. First, I argue contra Watkins that Kant’s laws of nature do not depend on acts of prescription in any literal sense. Second, I question how his generic conception of laws applies to empirical laws of nature and suggest that the worries about unknowability or contingency that he raises for contemporary alternatives may equally arise for empirical laws on Kant’s account. Finally, I discuss his claim that Kant’s a priori laws depend on the immutability of human cognitive capacities and ask how this immutability should be understood.

For Me, In My Present State: Kant on Judgments of Perception and Mere Subjective Validity,” Journal of Modern Philosophy 2 (9): 1-20, 2020. (Abstract)

Few of Kant’s distinctions have generated as much puzzlement and criticism as the one he draws in the Prolegomena between judgments of experience, which he describes as objectively and universally valid, and judgments of perception, which he says are merely subjectively valid. Yet the distinction between objective and subjective validity is central to Kant’s account of experience and plays a key role in his Transcendental Deduction of the categories. In this paper, I reject a standard interpretation of the distinction, according to which judgments of perception are merely subjectively valid because they are made without sufficient investigation. In its place, I argue that for Kant, judgments of perception are merely subjectively valid because they merely report sequences of perceptions had by a subject without claiming that what is represented by the perceptions is connected in the objects the perceptions are of. Whereas the interpretation I criticize undercuts Kant’s strategy in the Deduction, I argue, my interpretation illuminates it.

Two Feelings in the Beautiful: Kant on the Structure of Judgments of Beauty,” Philosophers’ Imprint 19 (34): 1-17, 2019. (Abstract)

In this paper, I propose a solution to a notorious puzzle that lies at the heart of Kant’s Critique of Judgment. The puzzle arises because Kant asserts two apparently conflicting claims: (1) F → J: A judgment of beauty is aesthetic, i.e., grounded in feeling. (2) J → F: A judgment of beauty could not be based on and must ground the feeling of pleasure in the beautiful. I argue that (1) and (2) are consistent. Kant’s text indicates that he distinguishes two feelings: the feeling of the harmony of the cognitive faculties that is the ground of judgments of beauty (F1 → J), and the feeling of pleasure that is its consequence (J → F2). I develop and defend a view of Kant’s account of the structure of judgments of beauty that incorporates this crucial distinction. Next, I argue that my view resolves another long-standing problem for Kant’s “Deduction” of judgments of beauty: it allows him to claim that the harmony of the faculties is a condition of judgment in general without implying, absurdly, that all judgments are pleasurable.

In Progress

“Kant’s Complete Solution to Hume’s Problem.”

“A Scandal of Philosophy: Kant's Refutation of External World Skepticism”